language.tex 21.8 KB
Newer Older
1
\newlength{\sk}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
space    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
2
\setlength{\sk}{-1.9pt}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
3
In this section we formalize the ideas we outlined in the introduction. We start by the definition of types followed by the language and its reduction semantics. The static semantics is the core of our work: we first present a declarative type system that deduces (possibly many) types for well-typed expressions and then the algorithms to decide whether an expression is well typed or not. 
4
5
6

\subsection{Types}

Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
7
\begin{definition}[Types]\label{def:types} The set of types \types{} is formed by the terms $t$ coinductively produced by the grammar:\vspace{-1.45mm}
8
9
10
11
12
\[
\begin{array}{lrcl}
\textbf{Types} & t & ::= & b\alt t\to t\alt t\times t\alt t\vee t \alt \neg t \alt \Empty 
\end{array}
\]
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
13
14
and that satisfy the following conditions
\begin{itemize}[nosep]
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
15
16
\item (regularity) every term has a finite number of different sub-terms;
\item (contractivity) every infinite branch of a term contains an infinite number of occurrences of the
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
17
arrow or product type constructors.\vspace{-1mm}
18
19
\end{itemize}
\end{definition}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
20
We use the following abbreviations: $
21
22
    t_1 \land t_2 \eqdef \neg (\neg t_1 \vee \neg t_2)$, 
    $t_ 1 \setminus t_2 \eqdef t_1 \wedge \neg t_2$, $\Any \eqdef \neg \Empty$.
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
23
$b$ ranges over basic types
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
24
(e.g., \Int, \Bool),
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
$\Empty$ and $\Any$ respectively denote the empty (that types no value)
and top (that types all values) types. Coinduction accounts for
recursive types and the condition on infinite branches bars out
ill-formed types such as 
$t = t \lor t$ (which does not carry any information about the set
denoted by the type) or $t = \neg t$ (which cannot represent any
set). 
It also ensures that the binary relation $\vartriangleright
\,\subseteq\!\types^{2}$ defined by $t_1 \lor t_2 \vartriangleright
t_i$, $t_1 \land t_2 \vartriangleright
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
35
t_i$, $\neg t \vartriangleright t$ is Noetherian.
36
This gives an induction principle on $\types$ that we
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
37
will use without any further explicit reference to the relation.\footnote{In a nutshell, we can do proofs by induction on the structure of unions and negations---and, thus, intersections---but arrows, products, and basic types are the base cases for the induction.} 
38
39
40
41
42
We refer to $ b $, $\times$, and $ \to $ as \emph{type constructors}
and to $ \lor $, $ \land $, $ \lnot $, and $ \setminus $
as \emph{type connectives}.

The subtyping relation for these types, noted $\leq$, is the one defined
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
43
by~\citet{Frisch2008} to which the reader may refer. A detailed description of the algorithm to decide it can be found in~\cite{Cas15}.
44
For this presentation it suffices to consider that
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
45
types are interpreted as sets of \emph{values} ({i.e., either
Victor Lanvin's avatar
Fixes    
Victor Lanvin committed
46
constants, $\lambda$-abstractions, or pairs of values: see
47
Section~\ref{sec:syntax} right below) that have that type, and that subtyping is set
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
48
containment (i.e., a type $s$ is a subtype of a type $t$ if and only if $t$
49
50
contains all the values of type $s$). In particular, $s\to t$
contains all $\lambda$-abstractions that when applied to a value of
51
type $s$, if their computation terminates, then they return a result of
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
52
type $t$ (e.g., $\Empty\to\Any$ is the set of all
53
54
55
56
functions\footnote{\label{allfunctions}Actually, for every type $t$,
all types of the form $\Empty{\to}t$ are equivalent and each of them
denotes the set of all functions.} and $\Any\to\Empty$ is the set
of functions that diverge on every argument). Type connectives
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
57
58
(i.e., union, intersection, negation) are interpreted as the
corresponding set-theoretic operators (e.g.,~$s\vee t$ is the
59
union of the values of the two types). We use $\simeq$ to denote the
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
60
symmetric closure of $\leq$: thus $s\simeq t$ (read, $s$ is equivalent to $t$) means that $s$ and $t$ denote the same set of values and, as such, they are semantically the same type.
61
62

\subsection{Syntax}\label{sec:syntax}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
63
The expressions $e$ and values $v$ of our language are inductively generated by the following grammars:\vspace{-1mm}
64
\begin{equation}\label{expressions}
65
\begin{array}{lrclr}  
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
66
67
  \textbf{Expr} &e &::=& c\alt x\alt ee\alt\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i} x.e\alt \pi_j e\alt(e,e)\alt\tcase{e}{t}{e}{e}\\[.3mm]
  \textbf{Values} &v &::=& c\alt\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i} x.e\alt (v,v)\\[-1mm]
68
69
\end{array}
\end{equation}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
wording    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
70
for $j=1,2$. In~\eqref{expressions}, $c$ ranges over constants
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
71
(e.g., \texttt{true}, \texttt{false}, \texttt{1}, \texttt{2},
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
...) which are values of basic types (we use $\basic{c}$ to denote the
basic type of the constant $c$); $x$ ranges over variables; $(e,e)$
denote pairs and $\pi_i e$ their projections; $\tcase{e}{t}{e_1}{e_2}$
denotes the type-case expression that evaluates either $e_1$ or $e_2$
according to whether the value returned by $e$ (if any) is of type $t$
or not; $\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i} x.e$ is a value of type
$\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i$ and denotes the function of parameter $x$
and body $e$. An expression has an intersection type if and only if it
has all the types that compose the intersection. Therefore,
intuitively, $\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i} x.e$ is a well-typed
value if for all $i{\in} I$ the hypothesis that $x$ is of type $s_i$
implies that the body $e$ has type $t_i$, that is to say, it is well
typed if $\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i} x.e$ has type $s_i\to
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
typos    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
85
t_i$ for all $i\in I$. Every value is associated to a most specific type (mst): the mst of $c$ is $\basic c$; the mst of
86
 $\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i} x.e$ is $\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i$; and, inductively,
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
87
88
the mst of a pair of values is the product of the mst's of the
values. We write $v\in t$ if the most specific type of $v$ is a subtype of $t$ (see Appendix~\ref{app:typeschemes} for the formal definition of $v\in t$ which  deals with some corner cases for negated arrow types).
89
90
91



92
\subsection{Dynamic semantics}\label{sec:opsem}
93

Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
94
The dynamic semantics is defined as a classic left-to-right call-by-value reduction for a $\lambda$-calculus with pairs, enriched with specific rules for type-cases. We have the following  notions of reduction:\vspace{-1.2mm}
95
96
\[
\begin{array}{rcll}
Kim Nguyễn's avatar
Kim Nguyễn committed
97
  (\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}s_i\to t_i} x.e)\,v &\reduces& e\subst x v\\[-.4mm]
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
98
99
  \pi_i(v_1,v_2) &\reduces& v_i & i=1,2\\[-.4mm]
  \tcase{v}{t}{e_1}{e_2} &\reduces& e_1 &v\in t\\[-.4mm] 
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
100
  \tcase{v}{t}{e_1}{e_2} &\reduces& e_2 &v\not\in t\\[-1.3mm]
101
102
\end{array}
\]
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
103
Contextual reductions are
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
104
105
106
defined by the following evaluation contexts:\\[1mm]
\centerline{\(
%\[
107
\Cx[] ::= [\,]\alt \Cx e\alt v\Cx \alt (\Cx,e)\alt (v,\Cx)\alt \pi_i\Cx\alt \tcase{\Cx}tee
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
108
109
%\]
\)}\\[1mm]
110
111
112
As usual we denote by $\Cx[e]$ the term obtained by replacing $e$ for
the hole in the context $\Cx$ and we have that $e\reduces e'$ implies
$\Cx[e]\reduces\Cx[e']$.
113

Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
114
\subsection{Static semantics}\label{sec:static}
115

116
While the syntax and reduction semantics are, on the whole, pretty
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
bla    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
117
standard, for what concerns the type system we will have to introduce several
118
unconventional features that we anticipated in
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
119
Section~\ref{sec:challenges} and are at the core of our work. Let
120
us start with the standard part, that is the typing of the functional
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
121
core and the use of subtyping, given by the following typing rules:\vspace{-1mm}
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
\begin{mathpar}
  \Infer[Const]
      { }
      {\Gamma\vdash c:\basic{c}}
      { }
  \quad
  \Infer[App]
      {
130
        \Gamma \vdash e_1: \arrow {t_1}{t_2}\quad
131
132
133
134
135
136
        \Gamma \vdash e_2: t_1
      }
      { \Gamma \vdash {e_1}{e_2}: t_2 }
      { }
  \quad
  \Infer[Abs+]
137
      {{\scriptstyle\forall i\in I}\quad\Gamma,x:s_i\vdash e:t_i}
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
      {
      \Gamma\vdash\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}\arrow {s_i} {t_i}}x.e:\textstyle \bigwedge_{i\in I}\arrow {s_i} {t_i}
      }
      { }
%      \Infer[If]
%            {\Gamma\vdash e:t_0\\
%            %t_0\not\leq \neg t \Rightarrow
%            \Gamma \cvdash + e t e_1:t'\\
%            %t_0\not\leq t \Rightarrow
%            \Gamma \cvdash - e t e_2:t'}
%            {\Gamma\vdash \ite {e} t {e_1}{e_2}: t'}
%            { }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
150
\vspace{-2mm} \\
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
151
      \Infer[Sel]
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
  {\Gamma \vdash e:\pair{t_1}{t_2}}
  {\Gamma \vdash \pi_i e:t_i}
  { }
  \qquad
  \Infer[Pair]
  {\Gamma \vdash e_1:t_1 \and \Gamma \vdash e_2:t_2}
  {\Gamma \vdash (e_1,e_2):\pair {t_1} {t_2}}
  { }
  \qquad
    \Infer[Subs]
      { \Gamma \vdash e:t\\t\leq t' }
      { \Gamma \vdash e: t' }
      { }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
165
  \qquad\vspace{-3mm}
166
\end{mathpar}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
167
These rules are quite standard and do not need any particular explanation besides those already given in Section~\ref{sec:syntax}. Just notice subtyping is embedded in the system by the classic \Rule{Subs} subsumption rule. Next we focus on the unconventional aspects of our system, from the simplest to the hardest.
168

Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
169
The first unconventional aspect is that, as explained in
170
Section~\ref{sec:challenges}, our type assumptions are about
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
171
expressions. Therefore, in our rules the type environments, ranged over
172
by $\Gamma$, map \emph{expressions}---rather than just variables---into
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
173
types. This explains why the classic typing rule for variables is replaced by a more general \Rule{Env} rule defined below:\vspace{-1mm}
174
175
176
177
178
179
\begin{mathpar}
  \Infer[Env]
      { }
      { \Gamma \vdash e: \Gamma(e) }
      { e\in\dom\Gamma }
  \qquad
180
  \Infer[Inter]
181
182
      { \Gamma \vdash e:t_1\\\Gamma \vdash e:t_2 }
      { \Gamma \vdash e: t_1 \wedge t_2 }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
183
      { }\vspace{-3mm}
184
\end{mathpar}
185
The \Rule{Env} rule is coupled with the standard intersection introduction rule \Rule{Inter}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
186
which allows us to deduce for a complex expression the intersection of
187
188
189
190
the types recorded by the occurrence typing analysis in the
environment $\Gamma$ with the static type deduced for the same
expression by using the other typing rules. This same intersection
rule is also used to infer the second unconventional aspect of our
191
system, that is, the fact that $\lambda$-abstractions can have negated
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
192
arrow types, as long as these negated types do not make the type deduced for the function empty:\vspace{-.5mm}
193
194
\begin{mathpar}
  \Infer[Abs-]
Mickael Laurent's avatar
Mickael Laurent committed
195
196
    {\Gamma \vdash \lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}\arrow {s_i} {t_i}}x.e:t}
    { \Gamma \vdash\lambda^{\wedge_{i\in I}\arrow {s_i} {t_i}}x.e:\neg(t_1\to t_2)  }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
197
    { ((\wedge_{i\in I}\arrow {s_i} {t_i})\wedge\neg(t_1\to t_2))\not\simeq\Empty }\vspace{-1mm}
198
\end{mathpar}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
%\beppe{I have doubt: is this safe or should we play it safer and
%  deduce $t\wedge\neg(t_1\to t_2)$? In other terms is is possible to
%  deduce two separate negation of arrow types that when intersected
%  with the interface are non empty, but by intersecting everything
%  makes the type empty? It should be safe since otherwise intersection
%  would not be admissible in semantic subtyping (see Theorem 6.15 in
%  JACM), but I think we should doube ckeck it.}
206
As explained in Section~\ref{sec:challenges}, we need to be able to
207
208
209
deduce for, say, the function $\lambda^{\Int\to\Int} x.x$ a type such
as $(\Int\to\Int)\wedge\neg(\Bool\to\Bool)$ (in particular, if this is
the term $e$ in equation \eqref{bistwo} we need to deduce for it the
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
210
211
type $(\Int\to t)\wedge\neg(\Int\to\neg\Bool)$, that is,
$(\Int\to t)\setminus(\Int\to\neg\Bool)$ ). But the sole rule \Rule{Abs+}
212
213
above does not allow us to deduce  negations of
arrows for abstractions: the rule \Rule{Abs-} makes this possible. As an aside, note that this kind
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
214
of deduction was already present in the system by~\citet{Frisch2008}
Kim Nguyễn's avatar
typo.    
Kim Nguyễn committed
215
though in that system this presence was motivated by the semantics of types rather than, as in our case,
216
217
218
219
220
by the soundness of the type system.

Rules \Rule{Abs+} and \Rule{Abs-} are not enough to deduce for
$\lambda$-abstractions all the types we wish. In particular, these
rules alone are not enough to type general overloaded functions. For
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
221
instance, consider this simple example of a function that applied to an
222
integer returns its successor and applied to anything else returns
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
223
224
225
\textsf{true}:\\[1mm]
\centerline{\(
%\[
226
\lambda^{(\Int\to\Int)\wedge(\neg\Int\to\Bool)} x\,.\,\tcase{x}{\Int}{x+1}{\textsf{true}}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
227
228
%\]
\)}\\[1mm]
229
Clearly, the expression above is well typed, but the rule \Rule{Abs+} alone
230
is not enough to type it. In particular, according to \Rule{Abs+} we
231
have to prove that under the hypothesis that $x$ is of type $\Int$ the expression
232
$(\tcase{x}{\Int}{x+1}{\textsf{true}})$ is of type $\Int$, too.  That is, that under the
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
233
hypothesis that $x$ has type $\Int\wedge\Int$ (we apply occurrence
234
typing) the expression $x+1$ is of type \Int{} (which holds) and that under the
235
hypothesis that $x$ has type $\Int\setminus\Int$, that is $\Empty$
236
237
(we apply once more occurrence typing), \textsf{true} is of type \Int{}
(which \emph{does not} hold). The problem is that we are trying to type the
238
second case of a type-case even if we know that there is no chance that, when $x$ is bound to an integer,
239
240
that case will be ever selected. The fact that it is never selected is witnessed
by the presence of a type hypothesis with  $\Empty$ type. To
241
avoid this problem (and type the term above) we add the rule
242
243
244
\Rule{Efq} (\emph{ex falso quodlibet}) that allows the system to deduce any type
for an expression that will never be selected, that is, for an
expression whose type environment contains an empty assumption:
245
246
247
248
\begin{mathpar}
  \Infer[Efq]
  { }
  { \Gamma, (e:\Empty) \vdash e': t }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
249
  { }\vspace{-3mm}
250
\end{mathpar}
251
252
253
Once more, this kind of deduction was already present in the system
by~\citet{Frisch2008} to type full fledged overloaded functions,
though it was embedded in the typing rule for the type-case. Here we
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
254
need the rule \Rule{Efq}, which is more general, to ensure the
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
255
256
property of subject reduction.
%\beppe{Example?}
257

Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
258
Finally, there remains one last rule in our type system, the one that
259
implements occurrence typing, that is, the rule for the
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
260
type-case:\vspace{-1mm}
261
262
263
264
\begin{mathpar}
    \Infer[Case]
        {\Gamma\vdash e:t_0\\
        %t_0\not\leq \neg t \Rightarrow
265
        \Gamma \evdash e t \Gamma_1 \\ \Gamma_1 \vdash e_1:t'\\
266
        %t_0\not\leq t \Rightarrow
267
        \Gamma \evdash e {\neg t} \Gamma_2 \\ \Gamma_2 \vdash e_2:t'}
268
        {\Gamma\vdash \tcase {e} t {e_1}{e_2}: t'}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
269
        { }\vspace{-3mm}
270
\end{mathpar}
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
The rule \Rule{Case} checks whether the expression $e$, whose type is
being tested, is well-typed and then performs the occurrence typing
analysis that produces the environments $\Gamma_i$'s under whose
hypothesis the expressions $e_i$'s are typed. The production of these
environments is represented by the judgments $\Gamma \evdash e
{(\neg)t} \Gamma_i$. The intuition is that when $\Gamma \evdash e t
\Gamma_1$ is provable then $\Gamma_1$ is a version of $\Gamma$
extended with type hypotheses for all expressions occurring in $e$,
type hypotheses that can be deduced assuming that the test $e\in t$
succeeds. Likewise, $\Gamma \evdash e {\neg t} \Gamma_2$ (notice the negation on $t$) extends
$\Gamma$ with the hypothesis deduced assuming that $e\in\neg t$, that
is, for when the test $e\in t$ fails.
283

284
All it remains to do is to show how to deduce judgments of the form
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
285
$\Gamma \evdash e t \Gamma'$. For that we first define how
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
286
287
to denote occurrences of an expression. These are identified by paths in the
syntax tree of the expressions, that is, by possibly empty strings of
288
289
290
291
292
293
characters denoting directions starting from the root of the tree (we
use $\epsilon$ for the empty string/path, which corresponds to the
root of the tree).

Let $e$ be an expression and $\varpi\in\{0,1,l,r,f,s\}^*$ a
\emph{path}; we denote $\occ e\varpi$ the occurrence of $e$ reached by
Kim Nguyễn's avatar
Kim Nguyễn committed
294
the path $\varpi$, that is (for $i=0,1$, and undefined otherwise)\vspace{-.4mm}
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
%% \[
%% \begin{array}{l}
%% \begin{array}{r@{\downarrow}l@{\quad=\quad}l}
%% e&\epsilon & e\\
%% e_0e_1& i.\varpi & \occ{e_i}\varpi\qquad i=0,1\\
%% (e_0,e_1)& l.\varpi & \occ{e_0}\varpi\\
%% (e_0,e_1)& r.\varpi & \occ{e_1}\varpi\\
%% \pi_1 e& f.\varpi & \occ{e}\varpi\\
%% \pi_2 e& s.\varpi & \occ{e}\varpi\\
%% \end{array}\\
%% \text{undefined otherwise}
%% \end{array}
%% \]
308
\[
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
309
\begin{array}{r@{\downarrow}l@{\quad=\quad}lr@{\downarrow}l@{\quad=\quad}lr@{\downarrow}l@{\quad=\quad}l}
Kim Nguyễn's avatar
Kim Nguyễn committed
310
311
e&\epsilon & e & (e_1,e_2)& l.\varpi & \occ{e_1}\varpi &\pi_1 e& f.\varpi & \occ{e}\varpi\\
e_0\,e_1& i.\varpi & \occ{e_i}\varpi \quad\qquad& (e_1,e_2)& r.\varpi & \occ{e_2}\varpi \quad\qquad&
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
spaces    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
312
\pi_2 e& s.\varpi & \occ{e}\varpi\\[-.4mm]
313
314
315
316
\end{array}
\]
To ease our analysis we used different directions for each kind of
term. So we have $0$ and $1$ for the function and argument of an
317
application, $l$ and $r$ for the $l$eft and $r$ight expressions forming a pair,
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
318
and $f$ and $s$ for the argument of a $f$irst or of a $s$econd projection. Note also that we do not consider occurrences
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
319
under $\lambda$'s (since their type is frozen in their annotations) and type-cases (since they reset the analysis).
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
space    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
320
321
%
The judgments  $\Gamma \evdash e t \Gamma'$ are then deduced by the following two rules:\vspace{-1mm} \begin{mathpar}
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
%        \Infer[Base]
%            { \Gamma \vdash e':t' }
%            { \Gamma \cvdash p e t e':t' }
%            { }
%            \qquad
%        \Infer[Path]
%            { \pvdash \Gamma p e t \varpi:t_1 \\ \Gamma,(\occ e \varpi:t_1) \cvdash p e t e':t_2 }
%            { \Gamma \cvdash p e t e':t_2 }
%            { }
    \Infer[Base]
      { }
333
      { \Gamma \evdash e t \Gamma }
334
335
336
      { }
    \qquad
    \Infer[Path]
337
338
      { \pvdash {\Gamma'} e t \varpi:t' \\ \Gamma \evdash e t \Gamma' }
      { \Gamma \evdash e t \Gamma',(\occ e \varpi:t') }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
space    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
339
      { }\vspace{-1.5mm}
340
\end{mathpar}
341
342
343
344
These rules describe how to produce by occurrence typing the type
environments while checking that an expression $e$ has type $t$. They state that $(i)$ we can
deduce from $\Gamma$ all the hypothesis already in $\Gamma$ (rule
\Rule{Base}) and that $(ii)$ if we can deduce a given type $t'$ for a particular
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
345
occurrence $\varpi$ of the expression $e$ being checked, then we can add this
346
hypothesis to the produced type environment (rule \Rule{Path}). The rule
347
\Rule{Path} uses a (last) auxiliary judgement $\pvdash {\Gamma}  e t
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
348
\varpi:t'$ to deduce the type $t'$ of the occurrence $\occ e \varpi$ when
349
350
351
352
353
checking $e$ against $t$ under the hypotheses $\Gamma$. This rule \Rule{Path} is subtler than it may appear at
first sight, insofar as the deduction of the type for $\varpi$ may already use
some hypothesis on $\occ e \varpi$ (in $\Gamma'$) and, from an
algorithmic viewpoint, this will imply the computation of a fix-point
(see Section~\ref{sec:typenv}). The last ingredient for our type system is the deduction of the
354
judgements of the form $\pvdash {\Gamma}  e t \varpi:t'$ where
355
$\varpi$ is a path to an expression occurring in $e$. This is given by the following set
356
357
358
of rules.
\begin{mathpar}
    \Infer[PSubs]
359
360
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t_1 \\ t_1\leq t_2 }
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t_2 }
361
        { }
362
        \quad
363
    \Infer[PInter]
364
365
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t_1 \\ \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t_2 }
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t_1\land t_2 }
366
        { }
367
        \quad
368
369
    \Infer[PTypeof]
        { \Gamma \vdash \occ e \varpi:t' }
370
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t' }
371
        { }
372
\vspace{-1.2mm}\\
373
    \Infer[PEps]
374
        { }
375
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \epsilon:t }
376
377
378
        { }
        \qquad
    \Infer[PAppR]
379
380
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.0:\arrow{t_1}{t_2} \\ \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t_2'}
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.1:\neg t_1 }
381
        { t_2\land t_2' \simeq \Empty  }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
382
\ifsubmission\vspace{-1.2mm}\\\else\end{mathpar}\begin{mathpar}\fi
383
    \Infer[PAppL]
384
385
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.1:t_1 \\ \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t_2 }
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.0:\neg (\arrow {t_1} {\neg t_2}) }
386
387
388
        { }
        \qquad
    \Infer[PPairL]
389
390
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:\pair{t_1}{t_2} }
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.l:t_1 }
391
        { }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
space    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
392
\vspace{-1.2mm}\\
393
    \Infer[PPairR]
394
395
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:\pair{t_1}{t_2} }
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.r:t_2 }
396
397
398
        { }
        \qquad
    \Infer[PFst]
399
400
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t' }
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.f:\pair {t'} \Any }
401
402
403
        { }
        \qquad
    \Infer[PSnd]
404
405
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi:t' }
        { \pvdash \Gamma e t \varpi.s:\pair \Any {t'} }
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
space    
Giuseppe Castagna committed
406
        { }\vspace{-1.9mm}
407
\end{mathpar}
408
409
410
These rules implement the analysis described in
Section~\ref{sec:ideas} for functions and extend it to products.  Let
us comment each rule in detail. \Rule{PSubs} is just subsumption for
411
the deduction $\vdashp$. The rule \Rule{PInter} combined with
412
413
\Rule{PTypeof} allows the system to deduce for an occurrence $\varpi$
the intersection of the static type of $\occ e \varpi$ (deduced by
414
\Rule{PTypeof}) with the type deduced for $\varpi$ by the other $\vdashp$ rules. The
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
415
rule \Rule{PEps} is the starting point of the analysis: if we are assuming that the test $e\in t$ succeeds, then we can assume that $e$ (i.e.,
416
$\occ e\epsilon$) has type $t$ (recall that assuming that the test $e\in t$ fails corresponds to having $\neg t$ at the index of the turnstyle).
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
417
The rule \Rule{PAppR} implements occurrence typing for
418
419
420
the arguments of applications, since it states that if a function maps
arguments of type $t_1$ in results of type $t_2$ and an application of
this function yields results (in $t'_2$) that cannot be in $t_2$
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
421
(since $t_2\land t_2' \simeq \Empty$), then the argument of this application cannot be of type $t_1$. \Rule{PAppL} performs the
422
423
424
425
occurrence typing analysis for the function part of an application,
since it states that if an application has type $t_2$ and the argument
of this application has type $t_1$, then the function in this
application cannot have type $t_1\to\neg t_2$. Rules \Rule{PPair\_}
426
are straightforward since they state that the $i$-th projection of a pair
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
427
that is of type $\pair{t_1}{t_2}$ must be of type $t_i$. So are the last two
428
429
430
431
432
rules that essentially state that if $\pi_1 e$ (respectively, $\pi_2
e$) is of type $t'$, then the type of $e$ must be of the form
$\pair{t'}\Any$ (respectively, $\pair\Any{t'}$).

This concludes the presentation of our type system, which satisfies
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
433
434
435
the property of safety, deduced, as customary, from the properties
of progress and subject reduction (\emph{cf.} Appendix~\ref{app:soundness}).
\begin{theorem}[type safety]
Giuseppe Castagna's avatar
Giuseppe Castagna committed
436
437
438
For every expression $e$ such that $\varnothing\vdash e:t$ either  $e$
diverges or there
exists a value $v$ of type $t$ such that $e\reduces^* v$.
439
\end{theorem}
440
441
442
443
444